RECORD: S253.1 Wallace, A. R. 1876. [Review of Lessons from nature by St. George Mivart], first notice. Academy (n.s) 9 (214): 562-563.

REVISION HISTORY: Body text helpfully provided by Charles H. Smith from his Alfred Russel Wallace Page http://people.wku.edu/charles.smith/wallace/S253.htm

NOTE: See a copy of this item from Darwin's private papers here.


[page] 562

Lessons From Nature, as manifested in Mind and Matter. By St. George Mivart, Ph.D., F.R.S., &c., &c. (London: John Murray, 1876.)

(First Notice.)

This book, though consisting chiefly of reprinted articles from periodicals, is a connected and very powerful criticism of modern philosophy, as exhibited in the works of Herbert Spencer, Mr. Darwin, Prof. Huxley, and other evolutionists. Not that Prof. Mivart is opposed to evolution. On the contrary, he upholds it strongly, and in some respects more consistently than many of his opponents; but he strenuously denies its power to account for the moral and higher intellectual nature of man as a development of the mind of brutes; while he can hardly find terms strong enough to express his condemnation of the purely material or nontheistic theory of the universe which, either expressly or implicitly, he finds in the writings of most of the eminent men above referred to.

The first three chapters deal with Self-existence, First Truths, and the External World; and it is held that our usual beliefs on these points are trustworthy, since it can be shown that, if we do not accept what are commonly held to be necessary truths, even the limited amount of real knowledge allowed us by philosophers turns out to be fallacious. Nothing, for example, has been more generally accepted than Mr. Mill's statement that all our knowledge is of "a series of states of consciousness." The most radical of modern sceptics have admitted this; yet Mr. Mivart shows conclusively that the same rigid logic which has compelled them to deny that we really know any more than this, if consistently followed, demonstrates that we must give up the "series," give up all past knowledge, all memory, and all "states of consciousness," and that all which really remains to us is the knowledge that "thoughts exist." For past thoughts can only be known to us as thoughts that we had thoughts, and memory as thoughts that we had a particular state or states of consciousness; but we have no more real knowledge that these "past thoughts" and "past states" ever existed than we have that an external world exists. Mr. Mill's "permanent possibilities of sensation" equally fall to the ground; for we cannot possibly "know" that any thing is permanent, or that we have ever existed except at the actual moment in which we are now thinking. The trustworthiness of memory as verified by experience is, therefore, from the sceptical point of view, as complete a fallacy as the trustworthiness of any of our other faculties.

In the chapter on "First Truths" reference is made to Helmholtz's notion of intelligent beings living and moving in the surface of a sphere, and capable of perceiving nothing beyond that surface; and to his argument that to such beings our geometrical axioms would not be true, because, for example, two parallel lines would enclose a space. Mr. Mivart pronounces this "the enunciation of a transparent fallacy by a man of eminence," because "unless geometrical were necessary truths, it would be impossible for Prof. Helmholtz to declare what would or would not be the necessary results attending such imaginary conditions." Whether this argument will be held valid by metaphysicians or mathematicians is doubtful; but a more obvious difficulty seems to have been overlooked by the propounders and advocates of the hypothesis in question. The inhabitants of the "surface of a sphere" (if at all approaching terrestrial proportions) could not possibly know or perceive that the surface was spherical, any more than we can perceive the surface of the earth immediately around us to be so. To them the surface in which they lived would be a plane surface. They are supposed to be intellectually capable of geometrical investigations, and would, therefore, arrive at the same geometrical axioms as our own. Only when they carried out extensive geodetical researches would they find the contradiction between theory and experiment; and this would surely lead them, as it has led us, to deduce the spherical form of their world-surface. To make the argument more apparently valid, it should have been stated that the supposed spherical surface must be very small, compared with the beings inhabiting it, so that each of their bodies would be perceptibly curved, and every line, however short, perceived to be curved. But in that case these beings could never possibly acquire any knowledge of straight or parallel lines, or of plane triangles, but only of spherical geometry, the laws and axioms of which would strictly agree with those of our spherical geometry. But with a knowledge that their geometry was spherical, would it not be almost certain that they would be able to develope plane geometry as a possibility, and demonstrate that, if they could but get out of their spherical surface, straight and parallel lines, with their necessary properties, would exist? On neither supposition does it seem at all clear that, given the mental power to appreciate geometrical truths and the faculties necessary to become acquainted with geometrical figures, any difference as to the axioms of geometry could possibly arise.

Mr. Mivart makes what seems to us an important correction of the views of Mill and Spencer as to necessary truths, in distinguishing between "that negative inconceivability which comes from impotence or lack of experience, and that positive, active, perception of impossibility which comes from intellectual power and light." Our inability to imagine unextended colour comes under the first head; our judgment that the three angles of a plane triangle are together equal to two right angles, under the second. The one is unthinkable, but it may be from such ignorance as a blind man has of colour and visual form; the falsehood of the other is unthinkable, because we see the affirmative to be absolutely and necessarily true, Mill and Helmholtz notwithstanding. In like manner our author objects to Mr. Spencer's statement of the inconceivability of any resemblance between the external world and the ideas we obtain of it through our sense and intellect; and maintains that our senses may and probably do give us an approximately correct, though necessarily very imperfect, knowledge of the properties of objective existences.

In the next chapter, on Language, we first meet with the expression of Mr. Mivart's radical divergence from Mr. Darwin. He maintains that brutes have no germ, rudiment or vestige whatever of the superior nature of man; that man alone possesses rational language, the power to communicate, not emotions only, but thoughts, by sounds or signs. Chapter V., on Duty and Pleasure, carries this divergence still further, being wholly occupied with a searching criticism of the well-known views of Darwin and Spencer on this subject. Mr. Mivart maintains that no act is truly moral which is not primarily performed with a distinct consciousness of its being right as distinguished from pleasant or beneficial; and to the objection that this would exclude those good actions of the highest natures which are performed without deliberation, and which we all admire, he replies:—

"An action which has ceased to be directly deliberate has ceased to be moral as a distinct act; but it is moral as the continuation of those preceding deliberate acts through which the good habit was originally formed, and the rapidity with which the will is directed in the case supposed may indicate the number and constancy of antecedent meritorious volitions."

Mr. Darwin's illustration, of a breach of etiquette often causing us as great and lasting pain as an offence against morality, is well answered by the remark, that in the one case we do not judge ourselves morally blameworthy, while in the other we do. But perhaps the best illustration of the inadequacy of praise and blame, however long continued, to produce a sense of right and wrong is the following:—

"What quality can have been more universally useful to social communities than courage? It has always been, and is still, greatly admired and highly appreciated, and is especially adapted, both directly and indirectly, to enable its possessors to become the fathers of succeeding generations. If the social instinct were the basis of the moral sense, it is infallibly certain that courage must have come to be regarded as supremely 'good,' and cowardice to be deserving of the deepest moral condemnation. And yet what is the fact? A coward feels probably self-contempt, and that he has incurred the contempt of his associates; but he does not feel 'wicked.' He is painfully conscious of his defective organisation; but he knows that an organisation, however defective, cannot itself constitute moral demerit. Similarly we,

[page] 563

the observers, despise, avoid, or hate a coward; but we can clearly understand that a coward may be a more virtuous man than another who abounds in animal courage."

Holding, as he does, the view, that man's higher intellectual and moral nature has not arisen by any mere development of the mind of brutes, Mr. Mivart is consistent in maintaining that we possess freedom of will, in the sense that this higher nature is capable of impelling us to act in direct opposition to those physical and emotional motives which alone determine the wills and acts of animals and of grosser human natures. Being incited to action by the sum of pleasures and motives, none of which may be injurious to ourselves or to our fellows, we are yet able to will and act differently if we think it abstractedly right to do so. This, of course, is no real answer to the necessitarians, but it accords with the inherent feeling of our freedom of will, and it marks the distinction of our animal and our moral nature; the one due to development and subject to the law of intellectual necessity, the other derived from a higher source and influenced by a radically distinct set of motives.

The next two chapters, "Man" and "The Brute," are very interesting. Much use is made of Mr. E. B. Tylor's works, and it is argued with great force that man differs fundamentally from brutes, and that his origin, so far as regards his mind at all events, is distinct from theirs. Brutes are said to be wholly devoid of reason, and the various cases adduced by Mr. Darwin and others as proving the contrary are carefully examined. An important point is made of the fact that, as we pass from the lower animals to those forms which, physically, most resemble man, we find no corresponding approach to him in mental powers. The Anthropoid apes are in no degree more intelligent than the dog, the horse, the elephant, or even the beaver; while the instances of apparent intelligence in the actions of insects, and even of snails, place them, in this respect, on a level with the gorilla. Mr. Mivart thinks that a book requires to be written on the "stupidity of animals," to balance the tendency to exaggerate so-called animal intelligence. A dog may have seen fuel put upon fire a hundred times, but he never puts on any himself to maintain the heat he so greatly enjoys; while Mr. Darwin himself states (on the authority of Mr. Harrison Weir) that, if a pair of birds "which would naturally remain mated for life be separated for a few weeks during the winter, and matched with other birds, the two, when brought together again rarely, if ever, recognise each other."

Chapter VIII., on "Likenesses in Animals and Plants," deals, first, with the phenomena of "mimicry" and maintains, on what seem to us to be insufficient grounds, that such likenesses could not have been produced by natural selection. The chief difficulty alleged is that "minute" and "insignificant" variations would not be useful enough to be preserved, while the number and variety of the variations would favour their mutual neutralisation and obliteration. This objection derives its chief force from a false premiss—that variations are exclusively or even usually "minute" or "insignificant" in the sense required. In the first edition of The Genesis of Species, Mr. Mivart used the word "infinitesimal" as applied to the variations supposed to be effective in the modification of animals by natural selection. This was a term Mr. Darwin never used, and, though he does speak of "extremely slight" variations being useful, this cannot be held to mean that they are usually so "minute" and "imperceptible" as not to be useful, which is what Professor Mivart's argument requires. However small a variation may be, if it is useful natural selection must come into play; and as a matter of fact every naturalist knows that variations are by no means slight. By an elaborate series of measurements, Mr. J. A. Allen has shown that in a large number of North American birds every part of the external structure varies in size from twelve to eighteen per cent. In general tint there is also great variation, but in the markings which distinguish species from species usually much less, probably due to the fact that these particular markings are in each case especially useful, and thus all decided variations get rapidly eliminated by natural selection. But there are other species in which a great variation of marking is a common phenomenon; so that there are no grounds whatever for the statement that the only variations occurring with sufficient frequency are minute or insignificant. Another incorrect assumption which runs through Mr. Mivart's argument on this point is that variations "in all conceivable directions" are constantly and simultaneously occurring. But this is not the fact. Variation is primarily indefinite, and in many, perhaps all, directions; but it is itself subject to laws and conditions, and thus certain species and certain localities are subject to definite preponderant variations, offering materials for natural selection to act upon to more advantage in some directions than in others. The so-called mimicry in plants seems to be a totally distinct phenomenon produced by different causes. In some cases similar external conditions of a very marked kind acting upon plants, widely separated indeed in our classifications but radically alike in fundamental structure, have led to such resemblances as the African Euphorbiaceae to the American Cacti, and the foliage of some Australian Mimosae to the Eucalypti. The case of certain Brazilian fruits belonging to different natural orders closely resembling each other is parallel to the peculiarities of form in unrelated species of Celebesian butterflies, and has no resemblance whatever to mimicry. Mr. Mivart seems to forget that mimicry among animals has been shown in almost in every case to be a protection to the mimicking species, and that this is its essential character; while no such protection has been even suggested in any one of the resemblances among plants which have been adduced as analogous to it. If there is one case more than another which simple variation and natural selection seem fully and completely to explain, it is that of mimicry; and the suggestion that there is an innate tendency implanted in certain races of animals and plants to assume the external semblance of creatures very different from them is utterly uncalled for, even if we adopt Mr. Mivart's view of the generally subordinate part played by natural selection.

The remainder of this chapter is devoted to an account of the various kinds of internal resemblance among animals, and in particular to the serial, lateral, vertical, and other homologies between the different parts of animals. Doubt is thrown on the extreme value of development as a guide to affinity, and it is maintained that an animal is to be classed according to what it is, not according to the mode by which it has become what it is. Thus, if it should ever be proved that birds have developed not from one, but from several distinct reptilian ancestors, they will be none the less all birds.

ALFRED R. WALLACE.


This document has been accessed 1972 times

Return to homepage

Citation: John van Wyhe, ed. 2012-. Wallace Online. (http://wallace-online.org/)

File last updated 26 September, 2012